April
15, 2023
Albert Einstein is the
world-famous physicist. This article was originally published in the first
issue of Monthly Review (May 1949). It was subsequently published in May 1998
to commemorate the first issue of MR‘s fiftieth year.
—The Editors
Is it advisable for one who is not an expert on economic and
social issues to express views on the subject of socialism? I believe for a
number of reasons that it is.
Let us first consider the question from the point of view of
scientific knowledge. It might appear that there are no essential
methodological differences between astronomy and economics: scientists in both
fields attempt to discover laws of general acceptability for a circumscribed
group of phenomena in order to make the interconnection of these phenomena as
clearly understandable as possible. But in reality such methodological
differences do exist. The discovery of general laws in the field of economics
is made difficult by the circumstance that observed economic phenomena are
often affected by many factors which are very hard to evaluate separately. In
addition, the experience which has accumulated since the beginning of the
so-called civilized period of human history has—as is well known—been largely
influenced and limited by causes which are by no means exclusively economic in
nature. For example, most of the major states of history owed their existence
to conquest. The conquering peoples established themselves, legally and
economically, as the privileged class of the conquered country. They seized for
themselves a monopoly of the land ownership and appointed a priesthood from
among their own ranks. The priests, in control of education, made the class
division of society into a permanent institution and created a system of values
by which the people were thenceforth, to a large extent unconsciously, guided
in their social behavior.
But historic tradition is, so to speak, of yesterday; nowhere
have we really overcome what Thorstein Veblen called “the predatory phase” of
human development. The observable economic facts belong to that phase and even
such laws as we can derive from them are not applicable to other phases. Since
the real purpose of socialism is precisely to overcome and advance beyond the
predatory phase of human development, economic science in its present state can
throw little light on the socialist society of the future.
Second, socialism is directed towards a social-ethical end.
Science, however, cannot create ends and, even less, instill them in human
beings; science, at most, can supply the means by which to attain certain ends.
But the ends themselves are conceived by personalities with lofty ethical
ideals and—if these ends are not stillborn, but vital and vigorous—are adopted
and carried forward by those many human beings who, half unconsciously,
determine the slow evolution of society.
For these reasons, we should be on our guard not to overestimate
science and scientific methods when it is a question of human problems; and we
should not assume that experts are the only ones who have a right to express
themselves on questions affecting the organization of society.
Innumerable voices have been asserting for some time now that
human society is passing through a crisis, that its stability has been gravely
shattered. It is characteristic of such a situation that individuals feel
indifferent or even hostile toward the group, small or large, to which they
belong. In order to illustrate my meaning, let me record here a personal
experience. I recently discussed with an intelligent and well-disposed man the
threat of another war, which in my opinion would seriously endanger the
existence of mankind, and I remarked that only a supra-national organization
would offer protection from that danger. Thereupon my visitor, very calmly and
coolly, said to me: “Why are you so deeply opposed to the disappearance of the
human race?”
I am sure that as little as a century ago no one would have so
lightly made a statement of this kind. It is the statement of a man who has
striven in vain to attain an equilibrium within himself and has more or less
lost hope of succeeding. It is the expression of a painful solitude and
isolation from which so many people are suffering in these days. What is the
cause? Is there a way out?
It is easy to raise such questions, but difficult to answer them
with any degree of assurance. I must try, however, as best I can, although I am
very conscious of the fact that our feelings and strivings are often
contradictory and obscure and that they cannot be expressed in easy and simple
formulas.
Man is, at one and the same time, a solitary being and a social
being. As a solitary being, he attempts to protect his own existence and that
of those who are closest to him, to satisfy his personal desires, and to
develop his innate abilities. As a social being, he seeks to gain the
recognition and affection of his fellow human beings, to share in their
pleasures, to comfort them in their sorrows, and to improve their conditions of
life. Only the existence of these varied, frequently conflicting, strivings
accounts for the special character of a man, and their specific combination
determines the extent to which an individual can achieve an inner equilibrium
and can contribute to the well-being of society. It is quite possible that the
relative strength of these two drives is, in the main, fixed by inheritance.
But the personality that finally emerges is largely formed by the environment
in which a man happens to find himself during his development, by the structure
of the society in which he grows up, by the tradition of that society, and by
its appraisal of particular types of behavior. The abstract concept “society”
means to the individual human being the sum total of his direct and indirect
relations to his contemporaries and to all the people of earlier generations.
The individual is able to think, feel, strive, and work by himself; but he
depends so much upon society—in his physical, intellectual, and emotional
existence—that it is impossible to think of him, or to understand him, outside
the framework of society. It is “society” which provides man with food,
clothing, a home, the tools of work, language, the forms of thought, and most
of the content of thought; his life is made possible through the labor and the
accomplishments of the many millions past and present who are all hidden behind
the small word “society.”
It is evident, therefore, that the dependence of the individual
upon society is a fact of nature which cannot be abolished—just as in the case
of ants and bees. However, while the whole life process of ants and bees is
fixed down to the smallest detail by rigid, hereditary instincts, the social
pattern and interrelationships of human beings are very variable and
susceptible to change. Memory, the capacity to make new combinations, the gift
of oral communication have made possible developments among human being which
are not dictated by biological necessities. Such developments manifest
themselves in traditions, institutions, and organizations; in literature; in
scientific and engineering accomplishments; in works of art. This explains how
it happens that, in a certain sense, man can influence his life through his own
conduct, and that in this process conscious thinking and wanting can play a
part.
Man acquires at birth, through heredity, a biological
constitution which we must consider fixed and unalterable, including the
natural urges which are characteristic of the human species. In addition,
during his lifetime, he acquires a cultural constitution which he adopts from
society through communication and through many other types of influences. It is
this cultural constitution which, with the passage of time, is subject to
change and which determines to a very large extent the relationship between the
individual and society. Modern anthropology has taught us, through comparative
investigation of so-called primitive cultures, that the social behavior of
human beings may differ greatly, depending upon prevailing cultural patterns
and the types of organization which predominate in society. It is on this that
those who are striving to improve the lot of man may ground their hopes: human
beings are not condemned, because of their biological constitution, to
annihilate each other or to be at the mercy of a cruel, self-inflicted fate.
If we ask ourselves how the structure of society and the
cultural attitude of man should be changed in order to make human life as
satisfying as possible, we should constantly be conscious of the fact that
there are certain conditions which we are unable to modify. As mentioned
before, the biological nature of man is, for all practical purposes, not
subject to change. Furthermore, technological and demographic developments of
the last few centuries have created conditions which are here to stay. In
relatively densely settled populations with the goods which are indispensable
to their continued existence, an extreme division of labor and a
highly-centralized productive apparatus are absolutely necessary. The
time—which, looking back, seems so idyllic—is gone forever when individuals or
relatively small groups could be completely self-sufficient. It is only a
slight exaggeration to say that mankind constitutes even now a planetary
community of production and consumption.
I have now reached the point where I may indicate briefly what
to me constitutes the essence of the crisis of our time. It concerns the
relationship of the individual to society. The individual has become more
conscious than ever of his dependence upon society. But he does not experience
this dependence as a positive asset, as an organic tie, as a protective force,
but rather as a threat to his natural rights, or even to his economic
existence. Moreover, his position in society is such that the egotistical
drives of his make-up are constantly being accentuated, while his social
drives, which are by nature weaker, progressively deteriorate. All human
beings, whatever their position in society, are suffering from this process of
deterioration. Unknowingly prisoners of their own egotism, they feel insecure,
lonely, and deprived of the naive, simple, and unsophisticated enjoyment of
life. Man can find meaning in life, short and perilous as it is, only through
devoting himself to society.
The economic anarchy of capitalist society as it exists today is,
in my opinion, the real source of the evil. We see before us a huge community
of producers the members of which are unceasingly striving to deprive each
other of the fruits of their collective labor—not by force, but on the whole in
faithful compliance with legally established rules. In this respect, it is
important to realize that the means of production—that is to say, the entire
productive capacity that is needed for producing consumer goods as well as
additional capital goods—may legally be, and for the most part are, the private
property of individuals.
For the sake of simplicity, in the discussion that follows I
shall call “workers” all those who do not share in the ownership of the means
of production—although this does not quite correspond to the customary use of
the term. The owner of the means of production is in a position to purchase the
labor power of the worker. By using the means of production, the worker
produces new goods which become the property of the capitalist. The essential
point about this process is the relation between what the worker produces and
what he is paid, both measured in terms of real value. Insofar as the labor
contract is “free,” what the worker receives is determined not by the real
value of the goods he produces, but by his minimum needs and by the
capitalists’ requirements for labor power in relation to the number of workers
competing for jobs. It is important to understand that even in theory the
payment of the worker is not determined by the value of his product.
Private capital tends to become concentrated in few hands,
partly because of competition among the capitalists, and partly because
technological development and the increasing division of labor encourage the
formation of larger units of production at the expense of smaller ones. The
result of these developments is an oligarchy of private capital the enormous
power of which cannot be effectively checked even by a democratically organized
political society. This is true since the members of legislative bodies are
selected by political parties, largely financed or otherwise influenced by
private capitalists who, for all practical purposes, separate the electorate
from the legislature. The consequence is that the representatives of the people
do not in fact sufficiently protect the interests of the underprivileged
sections of the population. Moreover, under existing conditions, private
capitalists inevitably control, directly or indirectly, the main sources of
information (press, radio, education). It is thus extremely difficult, and
indeed in most cases quite impossible, for the individual citizen to come to
objective conclusions and to make intelligent use of his political rights.
The situation prevailing in an economy based on the private
ownership of capital is thus characterized by two main principles: first, means
of production (capital) are privately owned and the owners dispose of them as
they see fit; second, the labor contract is free. Of course, there is no such
thing as a pure capitalist society in this sense. In particular, it should be
noted that the workers, through long and bitter political struggles, have
succeeded in securing a somewhat improved form of the “free labor contract” for
certain categories of workers. But taken as a whole, the present day economy
does not differ much from “pure” capitalism.
Production is carried on for profit, not for use. There is no
provision that all those able and willing to work will always be in a position
to find employment; an “army of unemployed” almost always exists. The worker is
constantly in fear of losing his job. Since unemployed and poorly paid workers
do not provide a profitable market, the production of consumers’ goods is
restricted, and great hardship is the consequence. Technological progress frequently
results in more unemployment rather than in an easing of the burden of work for
all. The profit motive, in conjunction with competition among capitalists, is
responsible for an instability in the accumulation and utilization of capital
which leads to increasingly severe depressions. Unlimited competition leads to
a huge waste of labor, and to that crippling of the social consciousness of
individuals which I mentioned before.
This crippling of individuals I consider the worst evil of
capitalism. Our whole educational system suffers from this evil. An exaggerated
competitive attitude is inculcated into the student, who is trained to worship
acquisitive success as a preparation for his future career.
I am convinced there is only one way to eliminate these grave
evils, namely through the establishment of a socialist economy, accompanied by
an educational system which would be oriented toward social goals. In such an
economy, the means of production are owned by society itself and are utilized
in a planned fashion. A planned economy, which adjusts production to the needs
of the community, would distribute the work to be done among all those able to
work and would guarantee a livelihood to every man, woman, and child. The
education of the individual, in addition to promoting his own innate abilities,
would attempt to develop in him a sense of responsibility for his fellow men in
place of the glorification of power and success in our present society.
Nevertheless, it is necessary to remember that a planned economy
is not yet socialism. A planned economy as such may be accompanied by the
complete enslavement of the individual. The achievement of socialism requires
the solution of some extremely difficult socio-political problems: how is it
possible, in view of the far-reaching centralization of political and economic
power, to prevent bureaucracy from becoming all-powerful and overweening? How
can the rights of the individual be protected and therewith a democratic
counterweight to the power of bureaucracy be assured?
Clarity about the aims and problems of socialism is of greatest
significance in our age of transition. Since, under present circumstances, free
and unhindered discussion of these problems has come under a powerful taboo, I
consider the foundation of this magazine to be an important public service.
No comments:
Post a Comment